The
first of the three sections begins with Irons. As this is a book review, I
intend to make my observations brief regarding my objections to some of Dr.
Irons’s conclusions. While I disagree with him on multiple levels, I do so respectfully.
Irons
- as did Smith - started off by defining his intention with the words “deity”
and “divine,” which was helpful in determining from the beginning what he was
essentially communicating. He recognizes that these can be used in multiple
senses and uses the example of emperor and hero veneration (although not in
those exact words) to make clear that this is not his context when employing the terminology. He stresses that ancient
heroes were nothing but mere men,
deified and perceived as having joined the gods in the Pantheon.
This
is where he first brings in the argument predominantly relied upon throughout the
entirety of his discourses. He interprets Jesus as the preexistent logos - the creator - thus placing Jesus
on the creator side of the creator-creature distinction. For Irons, this speaks
ontology:
“He is not man who became a god, but the Son of God who became man”
4.
I
found many of his arguments dependent on an anachronistic premise and laden
with metaphysical speculation not inherent to the text itself although he claims
to hold
“the formal principle of the Reformation, sola Scriptura” 149.
His language however, was not that of Scripture
alone. In developing his argument to positively relate Jesus’ unique identity
with Yahweh, Dr. Irons used the word
ontology/ontological a total of 42 times. This is not how the Bible speaks of
Jesus, despite hardships to ascertain the author’s intent beyond doubt in
various texts (most notably John, as this book bears out).
An
unwarranted and unproven premise upon which he built is the belief that “son of
God” signifies a statement of ontology. I found the following a telling
admission:
“I
hate to say, ‘Jesus is God,’ nor would I say ‘Jesus is not God.’ Instead I
prefer to say, as the New Testament says, that ‘Jesus is the Son of God.’
although it is possible to construe it in a valid sense, I am cautious about
the statement ‘Jesus is God,’ because the name ‘God’ (with the definite
article, ho theos) most frequently
and properly refers to the Father. ‘Jesus is God’ could be taken to mean ‘Jesus
is the Father,’ which would be modalism” 20.
His
apprehension to use the statement “Jesus is God” is curious due to the other
claims he is comfortable making without biblical veracity. The title “son of
God” has been the subject of much scholastic investment, and while there are
certainly those who would share in Irons’s opinion, this would hardly represent
the majority opinion on the matter. That the biblical use “son of God” denotes
ontological identity with God the Father, Yahweh,
is a pivotal distinction for him, but is built on shaky theological grounds
when a closer examination of this title is made within its rightful Hebraic framework.
On page
5 he makes the comment,
“Whether
it is the voice of God the Father from heaven saying, ‘This my beloved Son’ at
Jesus’ baptism and transfiguration, or Peter confessing, ‘You are the Christ,
the Son of the living God,” or Jesus before the high priest Caiaphas being
charged with blasphemy and condemned to death because he claimed to be the Son
of God, or the centurion at the scene of the crucifixion confessing, ‘Truly
this was the Son of God!’ – in all five key moments, the declaration of Jesus’
divine Sonship has the aura of being utterly significant and decisive.”
There
is no disputing these moments as “significant and decisive,” and much is left
to be examined regarding the nuances “son of God” communicates, but as “divine”
from Irons’s own definition predicates ontology, it is a baseless claim since
there is nothing in these texts to place the title in a metaphysical category. Both
Dixon and Smith voice their difficulties and present much more biblical evidence
than that with which Irons’s drew his conclusions. Dixon cites D. Garland and Smith,
N.T. Wright,
“we must stress that in the first century the regular Jewish
meaning of this title [Son of God] had nothing to do with an incipient
trinitarianism; it referred to the king as Israel’s representative” 39, Wright,
Jesus and the Victory of God, 485-86.
Sonship
cannot be extracted from its Hebraic roots:
“The psalms speak of the king as
son of God, and say he is begotten, not adopted. This language is mythical and
metaphorical rather than philosophical. It does not employ ontological
categories. But it should not be dismissed as ‘mere’ metaphor. It was a
powerful way of shaping perceptions about the special relationship between the
king and his god.” Collins, Son of God, 204.
Irons
is honest in his admission and rightfully careful to not "verge on
modalism," (19) but by saying Jesus shares the identity of Yahweh is essentially communicating the
same idea. He maintains that Jesus is the son of Yahweh, and in his way of reckoning believes this denotes an
ontological and eternally generated son.
"When
the son is exalted he receives the divine name, YHWH, because it is fitting in
terms of his ontological status. His receiving the divine name shows that he
shares in the identity of YHWH” 20.
Adequately refuted by both Dixon and Smith
is the fact that in the scope of scriptural use, actions that Yahweh is said to do or bearing his name
does not make one equal to, one in substance/essence with or ontologically identical
to him. This is a gross misrepresentation of biblical data.
Irons
uses various other passages and continues to regard them as ontological descriptions
of Jesus’ identity with Yahweh. This
is a difficulty, because he develops his argument on the basis of the false
notion that Sonship denotes ontology. “Son of God” and the later term “God the
Son” are not synonymous or interchangeable terms.
No comments:
Post a Comment